Fermat, Pierre de

Fermat, Pierre de
born Aug. 17, 1601, Beaumont-de-Lomagne, France
died Jan. 12, 1665, Castres

French mathematician.

Of Basque origin, Fermat studied law at Toulouse and developed interests in foreign languages, Classical literature, ancient science, and mathematics. A jurist by profession, he produced major mathematical breakthroughs independently and collaboratively. A contemporary of René Descartes, he discovered independently the basic principles of analytic geometry, but, because Fermat's work was published posthumously, the field became known as Cartesian geometry. He found equations for tangent lines to curves through processes equivalent to differentiation and was coauthor (with Blaise Pascal) of probability theory. His work in number theory, especially divisibility, led to some of its most important theorems. He seldom demonstrated his results, which led to a centuries-long quest to prove a famous conjecture that Fermat claimed was easily shown (see Fermat's last theorem).

Fermat, portrait by Roland Lefèvre; in the Narbonne City Museums, France

By courtesy of the Musees de la Ville de Narbonne, France

* * *

▪ French mathematician
Introduction
born August 17, 1601, Beaumont-de-Lomagne, France
died January 12, 1665, Castres
 French mathematician who is often called the founder of the modern theory of numbers (number theory). Together with René Descartes (Descartes, René), Fermat was one of the two leading mathematicians of the first half of the 17th century. Independently of Descartes, Fermat discovered the fundamental principle of analytic geometry. His methods for finding tangents to curves and their maximum and minimum points led him to be regarded as the inventor of the differential calculus. Through his correspondence with Blaise Pascal (Pascal, Blaise) he was a co-founder of the theory of probability.

Life and early work
      Little is known of Fermat's early life and education. He was of Basque origin and received his primary education in a local Franciscan school. He studied law, probably at Toulouse and perhaps also at Bordeaux. Having developed tastes for foreign languages, classical literature, and ancient science and mathematics, Fermat followed the custom of his day in composing conjectural “restorations” of lost works of antiquity. By 1629 he had begun a reconstruction of the long-lost Plane Loci of Apollonius, the Greek geometer of the 3rd century BC. He soon found that the study of loci, or sets of points with certain characteristics, could be facilitated by the application of algebra to geometry through a coordinate system. Meanwhile, Descartes had observed the same basic principle of analytic geometry, that equations in two variable quantities define plane curves. Because Fermat's Introduction to Loci was published posthumously in 1679, the exploitation of their discovery, initiated in Descartes's Géométrie of 1637, has since been known as Cartesian geometry.

      In 1631 Fermat received the baccalaureate in law from the University of Orléans. He served in the local parliament at Toulouse, becoming councillor in 1634. Sometime before 1638 he became known as Pierre de Fermat, though the authority for this designation is uncertain. In 1638 he was named to the Criminal Court.

Analyses of curves.
      Fermat's study of curves and equations prompted him to generalize the equation for the ordinary parabola ay = x2, and that for the rectangular hyperbola xy = a2, to the form an - 1y = xn. The curves determined by this equation are known as the parabolas or hyperbolas of Fermat according as n is positive or negative. He similarly generalized the Archimedean spiral r = aθ. These curves in turn directed him in the middle 1630s to an algorithm, or rule of mathematical procedure, that was equivalent to differentiation. This procedure enabled him to find equations of tangents to curves and to locate maximum, minimum, and inflection points of polynomial curves, which are graphs of linear combinations of powers of the independent variable. During the same years, he found formulas for areas bounded by these curves through a summation process that is equivalent to the formula now used for the same purpose in the integral calculus. Such a formula is:

      It is not known whether or not Fermat noticed that differentiation of xn, leading to nan - 1, is the inverse of integrating xn. Through ingenious transformations he handled problems involving more general algebraic curves, and he applied his analysis of infinitesimal quantities to a variety of other problems, including the calculation of centres of gravity and finding the lengths of curves. Descartes in the Géométrie had reiterated the widely held view, stemming from Aristotle, that the precise rectification or determination of the length of algebraic curves was impossible; but Fermat was one of several mathematicians who, in the years 1657–59, disproved the dogma. In a paper entitled “De Linearum Curvarum cum Lineis Rectis Comparatione” (“Concerning the Comparison of Curved Lines with Straight Lines”), he showed that the semicubical parabola and certain other algebraic curves were strictly rectifiable. He also solved the related problem of finding the surface area of a segment of a paraboloid of revolution. This paper appeared in a supplement to the Veterum Geometria Promota, issued by the mathematician Antoine de La Loubère in 1660. It was Fermat's only mathematical work published in his lifetime.

Disagreement with other Cartesian views
      Fermat differed also with Cartesian views concerning the law of refraction (the sines of the angles of incidence and refraction of light passing through media of different densities are in a constant ratio), published by Descartes in 1637 in La Dioptrique; like La Géométrie, it was an appendix to his celebrated Discours de la méthode. Descartes had sought to justify the sine law through a premise that light travels more rapidly in the denser of the two media involved in the refraction. Twenty years later Fermat noted that this appeared to be in conflict with the view espoused by Aristotelians that nature always chooses the shortest path. Applying his method of maxima and minima and making the assumption that light travels less rapidly in the denser medium, Fermat showed that the law of refraction is consonant with his “principle of least time. (Fermat's principle)” His argument concerning the speed of light was found later to be in agreement with the wave theory of the 17th-century Dutch scientist Christiaan Huygens, and in 1849 it was verified experimentally by A.-H.-L. Fizeau.

      Through the mathematician and theologian Marin Mersenne (Mersenne, Marin), who, as a friend of Descartes, often acted as an intermediary with other scholars, Fermat in 1638 maintained a controversy with Descartes on the validity of their respective methods for tangents to curves. Fermat's views were fully justified some 30 years later in the calculus of Sir Isaac Newton. Recognition of the significance of Fermat's work in analysis was tardy, in part because he adhered to the system of mathematical symbols devised by François Viète, notations that Descartes's Géométrie had rendered largely obsolete. The handicap imposed by the awkward notations operated less severely in Fermat's favourite field of study, the theory of numbers; but here, unfortunately, he found no correspondent to share his enthusiasm. In 1654 he had enjoyed an exchange of letters with his fellow mathematician Blaise Pascal on problems in probability (probability theory) concerning games of chance, the results of which were extended and published by Huygens in his De Ratiociniis in Ludo Aleae (1657).

Work on theory of numbers
      Fermat vainly sought to persuade Pascal to join him in research in number theory. Inspired by an edition in 1621 of the Arithmetic of Diophantus, the Greek mathematician of the 3rd century AD, Fermat had discovered new results in the so-called higher arithmetic, many of which concerned properties of prime numbers (those positive integers that have no factors other than 1 and themselves). One of the most elegant of these had been the theorem that every prime of the form 4n + 1 is uniquely expressible as the sum of two squares. A more important result, now known as Fermat's lesser theorem, asserts that if p is a prime number and if a is any positive integer, then ap - a is divisible by p. Fermat seldom gave demonstrations of his results, and in this case proofs were provided by Gottfried Leibniz, the 17th-century German mathematician and philosopher, and Leonhard Euler, the 18th-century Swiss mathematician. For occasional demonstrations of his theorems Fermat used a device that he called his method of “infinite descent,” an inverted form of reasoning by recurrence or mathematical induction. One unproved conjecture (Fermat prime) by Fermat turned out to be false. In 1640, in letters to mathematicians and to other knowledgeable thinkers of the day, including Blaise Pascal, he announced his belief that numbers of the form 22n + 1, known since as “numbers of Fermat,” are necessarily prime; but a century later Euler showed that 225 + 1 has 641 as a factor. It is not known if there are any primes among the Fermat numbers for n > 5. Carl Friedrich Gauss (Gauss, Carl Friedrich) in 1796 in Germany found an unexpected application for Fermat numbers when he showed that a regular polygon of N sides is constructible in a Euclidean sense if N is a prime Fermat number or a product of distinct Fermat primes. By far the best known of Fermat's many theorems is a problem known as his “great,” or “last,” theorem (Fermat's last theorem). This appeared in the margin of his copy of Diophantus' Arithmetica and states that the equation xn + yn = zn, where x, y, z, and n are positive integers, has no solution if n is greater than 2. This theorem remained unsolved until the late 20th century.

      Fermat was the most productive mathematician of his day. But his influence was circumscribed by his reluctance to publish.

Carl B. Boyer

Additional Reading
A substantial and authoritative summary of Fermat's achievements is provided in Michael S. Mahoney, The Mathematical Career of Pierre de Fermat (1601–1665) (1973). More specialized aspects of Fermat's work are treated in Carl B. Boyer, History of Analytic Geometry (1956, reissued 1988), and The Concepts of the Calculus (1949, reissued as The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development, 1959); and Isaac Todhunter, A History of the Mathematical Theory of Probability from the Time of Pascal to That of Laplace (1865, reprinted 1965).

* * *


Universalium. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Fermat, Pierre de — ► (1601 65) Matemático francés. Descubrió la geometría analítica. Fue el iniciador de la teoría de los números y del cálculo de probabilidades. * * * (17 ago. 1601, Beaumont de Lomagne, Francia–12 ene. 1665, Castres). Matemático francés. De… …   Enciclopedia Universal

  • Fermat , Pierre de — (1601–1665) French mathematician and physicist Fermat was one of the leading mathematicians of the early 17th century although not a professional mathematician. Born at Beaumont de Lomagne in France, he studied law and spent his working life as a …   Scientists

  • Fermat, Pierre de — (1601 1665)    mathematician    Born in Beaumont de Lomagne, Pierre de Fermat was a magistrate who had a passion for mathematics. In his youth, with his friend blaise pascal,he made a series of investigations into the properties of figurative… …   France. A reference guide from Renaissance to the Present

  • Fermat,Pierre de — Fer·mat (fĕr mäʹ), Pierre de. 1601 1665. French mathematician who developed number theory and probability theory. * * * …   Universalium

  • FERMAT, PIERRE DE —    a French mathematician, born near Montauban; made important discoveries in the properties of numbers, and with his friend Pascal invented a calculus of probabilities; was held in high esteem by Hallam, who ranks him next to Descartes (1601… …   The Nuttall Encyclopaedia

  • Pierre de Fermat — Naissance Première décennie du xviie siècle Beaumont de Lomagne (France) Décès 12 janvier 1665 Castres (France) Nationalité …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Fermat — Pierre de Fermat Pierre de Fermat Naissance Première décennie du XVIIesiècle Beaumont de Lomagne (France) Décès 12 janvier 1665 …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Pierre Fermat — Pierre de Fermat Pierre de Fermat Naissance Première décennie du XVIIesiècle Beaumont de Lomagne (France) Décès 12 janvier 1665 …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Pierre de fermat — Naissance Première décennie du XVIIesiècle Beaumont de Lomagne (France) Décès 12 janvier 1665 …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Pierre de Fermat — Born August 17, 1601( …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”