Austin, John

Austin, John
born March 3, 1790, Creeting Mill, Suffolk, Eng.
died Dec. 1859, Weybridge, Surrey

British jurist.

Although initially unsuccessful in his law practice (1818–25), his analytical mind and intellectual honesty impressed colleagues, and he was named the first professor of jurisprudence at University College, London (1826). Distinguished men attended his lectures, but he failed to attract students, and he resigned his chair in 1832. His writings, especially The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (1832), sought to distinguish law from morality. He also helped to define jurisprudence as the analysis of fundamental legal concepts, as distinct from the criticism of legal institutions, which he called the "science of legislation." His work, largely unrecognized in his lifetime, influenced later jurists, including Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.

* * *

▪ English jurist
Introduction
born March 3, 1790, Creeting Mill, Suffolk, Eng.
died December 1859, Weybridge, Surrey

      English jurist whose writings, especially The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (1832), advocated a definition of law (law, philosophy of) as a species of command and sought to distinguish positive law from morality. He had little influence during his lifetime outside the circle of Utilitarian supporters of Jeremy Bentham (Bentham, Jeremy). His authority came posthumously.

Life
      Austin began to study law in 1812 after five years in the army and from 1818 to 1825 practiced unsuccessfully at the chancery bar. His powers of rigorous analysis and his uncompromising intellectual honesty deeply impressed his contemporaries, and in 1826, when University College, London, was founded, he was appointed its first professor of jurisprudence, a subject that had previously occupied an unimportant place in legal studies. He spent the next two years in Germany studying Roman law and the work of German experts on modern civil law whose ideas of classification and systematic analysis exerted an influence on him second only to that of Bentham. Both Austin and his wife, Sarah, were ardent Utilitarians, intimate friends of Bentham and of James and John Stuart Mill (Mill, John Stuart), and much concerned with legal reform. Austin's first lectures, in 1828, were attended by many distinguished men, but he failed to attract students and resigned his chair in 1832. In 1834, after delivering a shorter but equally unsuccessful version of his lectures, he abandoned the teaching of jurisprudence. He was appointed to the Criminal Law Commission in 1833 but, finding little support for his opinions, resigned in frustration after signing its first two reports. In 1836 he was appointed a commissioner on the affairs of Malta. The Austins then lived abroad, chiefly in Paris, until 1848, when they settled in Surrey, where Austin died in 1859.

Work
      Austin's best known work, a version of part of his lectures, is The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, published in 1832. Here, in order to clarify the distinction between law and morality, which he considered to be blurred by doctrines of Natural Law, he elaborated his definition of law as a species of command. According to Austin, commands are expressions of desire that another shall do or forbear from some act and are accompanied by a threat of punishment (the “sanction”) for disobedience. Commands are laws “simply and properly so-called” when they prescribe courses of conduct, not specific acts, and are “set” by the “sovereign” (i.e., the person or persons to whom a society renders habitual obedience and who render no such obedience to others). This is the mark distinguishing “positive law” both from the fundamental principles of morality, which are the “law of God,” and from “positive morality,” or manmade rules of conduct, such as etiquette, conventional morality, and international law, which do not emanate from a sovereign. The Province also contains a version of Utilitarianism in which “utility” is regarded as the index of God's commands and the test of the moral quality of general rules of conduct rather than of particular actions.

      Austin viewed the doctrines in The Province as “merely prefatory” to the study that he termed “general jurisprudence”: the exposition and analysis of the fundamental notions forming the framework of all mature legal systems. He devoted the main part of his lectures (published in 1863) to an analysis of such “pervading notions” as those of right, duty, persons, status, delict, and sources of law. Austin distinguished this general, or analytical, jurisprudence from the criticism of legal institutions, which he called the “science of legislation”; he thought both were important parts of legal education.

Assessment
      Bouts of nervous illness and self-distrust prevented Austin from fully utilizing his great powers; his life, as his widow wrote, was one of “unbroken disappointment and failure,” in ironic contrast with his posthumous fame and influence. A long succession of English writers have echoed or elaborated his doctrines or, when opposing them, have accepted his conception of the analysis of legal concepts as the central concern of jurisprudence. In the United States jurists such as J.C. Gray and Oliver Wendell Holmes welcomed his bold distinction between law and morality as a major clarification.

      The reaction to Austin's work at the turn of the century was severe. His command theory was condemned as a misidentification of all law with the product of legislation and a distortion of many types of legal rule. The severance of a purely analytical jurisprudence from moral criticism of law was criticized as sterile verbalism obscuring the social function of law and the judicial process. Some critics consider that Austin's doctrine of sovereignty confuses the ideas of legal authority and political power; others hold “legal positivism” responsible for subservience to state tyranny or absolutism.

      Some of these criticisms are well founded, but even so Austin's work is of permanent value. The rigour and clarity of his analysis have demonstrated the complexity of many important legal and political concepts and the perennial need for just such an analytical study as he proposed, and repeated efforts to show precisely where his simple distinctions between law and morality are wrong have increased the understanding of both.

Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart

Additional Reading
Works describing John Austin's jurisprudence include John Stuart Mill, “Austin on Jurisprudence,” in Dissertations and Discussions, vol. 4, pp. 157–226 (1874); R.A. Eastwood and G.W. Keeton, The Austinian Theories of Law and Sovereignty (1929); and E.M. Campbell, John Austin and Jurisprudence in Nineteenth Century England (1959). Biographies of Austin include W.L. Morison, John Austin (1982); Wilfrid E. Rumble, The Thought of John Austin: Jurisprudence, Colonial Reform, and the British Constitution (1985); and G.J. Warnock, J.L. Austin (1989; reissued 1991).

* * *


Universalium. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать реферат

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Austin, John — • An English lawyer and writer, born 1613 at Walpole, in Norfolk; died London, 1669 Catholic Encyclopedia. Kevin Knight. 2006. Austin, John     John Austin …   Catholic encyclopedia

  • Austin, John — (1790–1859) British philosopher of law. Born in London, after a brief career in the army Austin was called to the Bar in 1818. With his wife, Sarah Taylor, he was closely associated with Bentham and his circle. When the university of London was… …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Austin, John Langshaw — ▪ British philosopher born March 28, 1911, Lancaster, Lancashire, Eng. died Feb. 8, 1960, Oxford       British philosopher best known for his individualistic analysis of human thought derived from detailed study of everyday language.       After… …   Universalium

  • Austin, John Langshaw — (1911–1960) British linguistic philosopher. Austin was educated and taught at Oxford, where he worked all his life except for a distinguished period in the Intelligence service during the Second World War. He had a classical and scholarly… …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Austin, John — (3 mar. 1790, Creeting Mill, Suffolk, Inglaterra–dic. 1859, Weybridge, Surrey). Jurista británico. Aunque tuvo un comienzo de poco éxito en el ejercicio de la profesión (1818–25), su mente analítica y su honestidad intelectual impresionaron a sus …   Enciclopedia Universal

  • AUSTIN, JOHN —    a distinguished English jurist, professor of Jurisprudence in London University; mastered the science of law by the study of it in Germany, but being too profound in his philosophy, was unsuccessful as professor; his great work, The Province… …   The Nuttall Encyclopaedia

  • Austin, John — (1790 1859)    Jurist, served in the army in Sicily and Malta, but, selling his commission, studied law, and was called to the Bar 1818. He did not long continue to practise, but devoted himself to the study of law as a science, and became… …   Short biographical dictionary of English literature

  • John Austin — Austin, John …   Philosophy dictionary

  • John L. Austin — John Langshaw Austin (* 26. März 1911 in Lancaster; † 8. Februar 1960 in Oxford) war englischer Philosoph und der Begründer der Sprechakttheorie. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Biographie 2 Philosophische Ansichten 3 …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • John Austin (legal philosopher) — John Austin (1790 1859) was a noted British jurist and published extensively concerning the philosophy of law and jurisprudence.Austin served with the British Army in Sicily and Malta, but sold his officer s commission to study law. He became a… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”